Prof.
Bryan Caplan
bcaplan@gmu.edu
http://www.bcaplan.com
Advanced
Public Choice
Lecture 3:
Wittman and Democratic Failure
I.
Critiques of the Economic Approach
A.
Critics of the economic approach to politics dislike its
"economistic" assumptions. Public choice allegedly ignores the most
important features of political life:
1.
Morality
2.
Community
3.
Public-spirited politicians
4.
Sincere public debate
5.
Efforts to "raise awareness"
B.
Critics also dislike the conclusions. Public choice economists always seem to be
pointing out the failures of democracy, which in the traditional view is
virtually a sacred institution.
C.
The thrust of the traditional response: "Sure, given your
economistic assumptions, all of your pessimistic conclusions about democracy
follow. But those economistic
assumptions are wrong, and democracy is working just fine. And if it's not working fine, the solution is
more democracy."
D.
In other words, the critics grant that the public choice story is
internally consistent, but reject its "economistic" starting point,
and thereby avoid the conclusion that democracy doesn't work well.
E.
My overall judgment: While economists definitely have important things
to learn from other disciplines (e.g. the failure of the SIVH), the sound
criticisms are pretty easy to incorporate into the economic approach.
II.
Wittman's Challenge to Orthodox Public Choice
A.
Donald Wittman of UC Santa Cruz offers a radically different critique
of public choice economics.
B.
Wittman does not object to
public choice's "economistic" approach.
C.
Instead, Wittman complaint is that so much of public choice is simply
bad economics.
D.
He claims that standard public choice arguments generally depend upon
extremely dubious assumptions. These can
be boiled down to:
1.
"Extreme voter stupidity"
2.
"Serious lack of competition"
3.
"Excessively high negotiation/transfer costs"
E.
Wittman's contrasting conclusion: The standard tools of microeconomic
analysis show that political markets work just as well as economic markets.
F.
As a corollary, Wittman argues that the political failures emphasized
in public choice theory are largely imaginary.
G.
Related point: Yes, people in the public sector are
self-interested. So what? Yes, they have acquired more power this
century, but again, so what? When
self-interested actors in markets increase their market share, few economists
get alarmed. How does that differ from
self-interested bureaucrats expanding their power?
III.
How to Think Like Wittman, I: Voter Ignorance Is Not a Serious Problem
A.
Many public choice arguments, according to Wittman, assume
"extreme voter stupidity."
B.
Normally, of course, public choice economists talk about
"ignorance" or "lack of information," rather than "stupidity." But Wittman argues that the assumption of
voter stupidity is implicit.
B.
Wittman's Principle #1: Voter
ignorance is not a serious problem.
C.
Why? First, the amount of
information held by voters has been underestimated.
1.
Party labels are "brand names" that drastically reduce
information costs.
2.
Politicians pay to inform voters by advertising, giving speeches, and
so on; voters don't have to pay to inform themselves.
a)
Ex: One politician takes "dirty money." The other side has a strong incentive to let
the public know.
3.
There are many private side benefits of acquiring political knowledge.
a)
Ex: Investors need to know what government policy will do in order to
pick stocks. When they go to vote, they
can easily rely on information they acquired for quite different reasons.
4.
Voters may just be storing their information in an "inarticulate
format." People often just take
information as it arrives, adjust their conclusion, and then forget the
information, but remember the conclusion. Thus, written tests of political knowledge
don't prove much.
D.
Second, informed judgments can be made with little information.
1.
Voters have many "cognitive shortcuts." Voters can simply ask their preferred experts
for information. Application: Just as I
don't need to know anything about heart surgery to get a first-rate bypass
operation, I don't need to know anything about current gun control proposals to
vote intelligently about gun control. If
I like guns, I just vote the NRA line; if I don't like guns, I follow the
advice of Citizens for Gun Control.
2.
Voters only need to know which of two candidates is closer to their bliss point; they don't
need to know candidates' exact locations.
3.
Analogy between stock markets and elections. Stock markets reflect information well even
though most investors are highly ignorant.
E.
Third, the deleterious effect of biased information has been overstated.
1.
Remember the Principle of Aggregation?
Even if people are highly ignorant, their random errors will cancel
out. Ignorance does not mean systematic bias.
2.
"To be uninformed about a policy does not imply that voters have
biased estimates of its effects. For
example, to be uninformed about the nature of pork-barrel projects in other
congressional districts does not mean that voters tend to underestimate the
effects of pork barrel - it is quite possible that the uninformed exaggerate
both the extent and the negative consequences of pork-barrel projects."
3.
Voters can discount, or simply ignore, information from biased or
questionable sources. If the media has a
"liberal bias," then voters can easily adjust. ("Sure, Koppel
said we need more money for the EPA, but what do you expect, he's a big
liberal?")
4.
Worst case: If you "can't trust" the available sources,
don't!
F.
Fourth, the effect of unresolved asymmetric information in politics is to make
government inefficiently small, not inefficiently large.
1.
Just as it is naive to think that asymmetric information helps used car
dealers sell cars, it is naive to think that asymmetric information helps
politicians create Big Government.
G.
Public choice economists' focus on "rational ignorance," is,
therefore, rather silly. Consumers and
investors are also rationally ignorant about a great deal, but they know enough for markets to work well. Similarly, voters know enough for democracy to work well.
H.
Moreover, the Principal of Aggregation assures good outcomes even in
the worst case scenario. (Wittman even
adds that democracy handles severe ignorance better than markets because aggregation protects the most
clueless).
I.
To reach their standard conclusions about political failure, then,
ignorance is not enough. They need to
assume that voters are "stupid" or irrational, something most economists are unwilling to do.
IV.
How to Think Like Wittman, II: "Serious Lack of Competition"
A.
Many other public choice arguments assume, in Wittman's phrase, a
"serious lack of competition."
B.
While public choice economists spend a great deal of energy studying
political competition, they frequently see strong monopolistic elements as well
(leading to support for things like term limits).
C.
Wittman's Principle #2: Politics,
like the market, is competitive.
D.
Why? First, reputation matters.
1.
If politicians break promises, voters hold it against them. If they do a good job, they reward them. Even if politicians only stay in one office
for a few years, they want to build up a good name in order to rise to higher
offices.
2.
Even when politicians plan on leaving politics entirely, their party
rewards them for protecting the party's image.
3.
Parties accordingly "vet" would-be candidates for sincere
ideological commitment.
4.
Remember the theory of optimal punishment: Voters can adjust for a
small probability of detection with harsh punishment. Politicians can destroy their whole
reputation with one mistake.
E.
Second, political races are at least as competitive as markets.
1.
Politics is full of "political entrepreneurs" who want to
stage a successful "takeover" (gain power) by locating unpopular
policies and campaigning to change them.
2.
Incumbent politicians know this, so they strive to preemptively adjust policy to please the electorate.
3.
High rates of reelection prove NOTHING.
"The main reason for high rates of incumbent success is... They are
the best. That is why they won in the
first place and why they are likely to win again."
4.
Similarity of platforms also proves NOTHING. Similar prices are actually a sign of competition
in markets; so are similar platforms in politics.
5.
Alleged "barriers to entry" are usually minimal. Campaign contributions are just another sign
of a serious candidate. If contributions
were basically bribes to induce politicians to act against voter interests,
political advertising would be counter-productive! Voters would vote against candidates because they had so much money behind
them.
6.
Similarly, third parties can't win because voters don't like them, not
because "the system" is against them.
7.
Ex: The case of Perot shows that it is easy for a third-party candidate
with serious mass support to enter at the highest level.
8.
"Negative" advertising is much more common in elections than
markets. Doesn't this suggest that
elections are actually more competitive?
And there is a simple reason, too: Elections, unlike markets, are
zero-sum games.
9.
Don't forget Tiebout-type competition.
F.
Third, empirical evidence
shows a strong link between voter preferences and legislative behavior.
G.
Wittman's bottom line: In markets, economists are usually skeptical
about collusion. Why are they less
skeptical in politics? How is the grand
electoral conspiracy maintained?
V.
How to Think Like Wittman, III: "Excessively High
Negotiation/Transfer Costs"
A.
Finally, public choice economists often argue that transactions costs
prevent more efficient policies from replacing the status quo.
1.
Ex: A special interest "blocks" changes harmful to its
interests, and it is "too hard" to buy them off.
B.
This brings us to Wittman's Principle #3: Political bargaining can eliminate any remaining significant
inefficiencies.
C.
Why? Democracy is designed to have low
transactions costs.
1.
Majority rule is cheaper than the unanimity required by markets.
2.
Representative democracy (as opposed to direct democracy) drastically
reduces transactions costs. Instead of 300
M Americans bargaining, we have a few hundred Congressmen and Senators
bargaining. (The same logic holds for
committees).
3.
Log-rolling can turn efficient but unpopular policies into efficient
AND popular policies.
4.
Long-term political contracts are rarely legally enforceable. But reputation - of both parties and
individual politicians - accomplishes the same thing.
5.
Interest groups also reduce transactions costs by giving legislators
information.
VI.
Wittman's Sampler, I: Pork Barrel Politics
A.
Pork barrel politics allegedly stem from the geographic nature of
representative. Every Congressman wants
to "bring home the pork" to his district.
B.
Reply #1: Presidents, governments, and other non-geographically-based
politicians often favor larger expenditures than legislatures.
C.
Reply #2: Many programs can be simultaneously abolished with an Omnibus
Repeal Bill (like the base closings bill).
D.
Reply #3: Political parties can take credit for "universal"
policies.
E.
Public choice economists sometimes say that political bargaining fails
because voters won't accept "blatant transfers." (Think of the NJ Turnpike workers).
F.
Reply #4: Wittman calls this knife-edge
stupidity. How come voters can
recognize efficient transfers but not inefficient transfers?
VII.
Wittman's Sampler, II: Concentrated Versus Diffuse Interests
A.
Ever since Olson, public choice economists have been impressed by the
ability of interest groups to solve their internal collective action problem in
order to take advantage of the disorganized majority. Standard examples:
1.
Tariffs
2.
Subsidies
3.
Teachers' unions
4.
NRA
B.
Reply #1: Mathematical improbability: Even if politicians lose only a
small fraction of majority's votes, it will rarely be balanced by large
fraction of interest group member's votes.
C.
Reply #2: Interest groups compete with each other, directly or
indirectly.
D.
Reply #3: Competing politicians can advertise their opponents' reliance
on special interest money. ("He took $10 M from the tobacco lobby.")
E.
Reply #4: Politicians realize interest groups are biased, and discount
their advice accordingly.
F.
Reply #5: Special interests win in referenda, too. Ex: Gun control.
G.
Reply #6: Total level of donations is very small, suggesting that
politicians aren't selling much of value.
VIII.
Validity Versus Soundness
A.
Wittman points out that there are four logically possible positions to
take on the efficiency of markets and democracy:
1.
Position #1: Markets fail, democracy works. (View typical of social democrats).
2.
Position #2: Markets work,
democracy fails. (View typical of public choice economists).
3.
Position #3: Markets fail, democracy fails. (View typical of hard-line Marxists).
4.
Position #4: Markets work, democracy works. (Wittman's view).
B.
Wittman's goal: End economists' "schizophrenia."
C.
Many public choice economists think that Wittman's arguments are poor.
D.
But we must keep a basic logical distinction between validity
and soundness firmly in mind.
1.
An argument is valid if it
logically follows from its assumptions.
2.
An argument is sound if it
logically follows from its assumptions AND those assumptions are true.
E.
On the whole, I think Wittman's arguments are usually valid.
He is definitely on to something when he points out other economists'
"schizophrenia."
F.
However, I strongly doubt that many of Wittman's arguments are sound.
He reasons carefully from his assumptions, but rarely considers the
possibility that some of these assumptions are deeply wrong.
G.
If Wittman's assumptions are wrong but widely-held, successful
critiques of Wittman will probably have wide-ranging ramifications for public
choice (as we will see in the next three weeks).