Prof.
Bryan Caplan
bcaplan@gmu.edu
http://www.bcaplan.com
Econ
410
Weeks 10-11:
Wittman's Myth of Democratic Failure
I.
Critiques of the Economic Approach
A.
Public choice is a self-conscious attack on the traditional,
"public interest," view of government.
B.
Many people continue to (more or less) adhere to the traditional view
even today.
C.
As one might expect, advocates of the traditional view have harshly
criticized the public choice alternative.
D.
Critics dislike its "economistic" assumptions. Public choice allegedly ignores the most
important features of political life:
1.
Morality
2.
Community
3.
Public-spirited politicians
4.
Sincere public debate
5.
Efforts to "raise awareness"
E.
Critics also dislike the conclusions. Public choice economists always seem to
be pointing out the failures of democracy, which in the traditional view is
virtually a sacred institution.
F.
The thrust of the traditional response: "Sure, given your
economistic assumptions, all of your pessimistic conclusions about democracy
follow. But those economistic
assumptions are wrong, and democracy is working just fine. And if it's not working fine, the
solution is more democracy."
G.
In other words, the critics grant that the public choice story is
internally consistent, but reject its "economistic" starting point,
and thereby avoid the conclusion that democracy doesn't work well.
H.
My overall judgment: While economists definitely have important things
to learn from other disciplines (e.g. the failure of the SIVH), the sound
criticisms are pretty easy to incorporate into the economic approach.
II.
Wittman's Challenge to Orthodox Public Choice
A.
Donald Wittman, an economics professor at UC Santa Cruz, offers a
radically different critique of public choice economics.
B.
Wittman does not object to public choice's
"economistic" approach.
C.
Instead, Wittman complaint is that so much of public choice is simply
bad economics.
D.
He claims that standard public choice arguments generally depend upon
extremely dubious assumptions.
These can be boiled down to:
1.
"Extreme voter stupidity"
2.
"Serious lack of competition"
3.
"Excessively high negotiation/transfer costs"
E.
Wittman's contrasting conclusion: The standard tools of microeconomic
analysis show that political markets work just as well as economic markets.
F.
As a corollary, Wittman argues that the political failures emphasized
in public choice theory are largely imaginary.
G.
Related point: Yes, people in the public sector are
self-interested. But so what? And yes, they have acquired more power
this century, but again, so what?
When self-interested actors in markets increase their market share, few
economists get alarmed. How does
that differ from self-interested bureaucrats expanding their power?
III.
How to Think Like Wittman, I: Voter Ignorance Is Not a Serious Problem
A.
Many public choice arguments, according to Wittman, assume
"extreme voter stupidity."
B.
Normally, of course, public choice economists talk about
"ignorance" or "lack of information," rather than "stupidity." But Wittman argues that the assumption
of voter stupidity is implicit.
B.
Wittman's Principle #1: Voter
ignorance is not a serious problem.
C.
Why? First, the amount
of information held by voters has been underestimated.
1.
Party labels are "brand names" that drastically reduce
information costs.
2.
Politicians pay to inform voters by advertising, giving speeches, and
so on; voters don't have to pay to inform themselves.
3.
Ex: One politician takes "dirty money." The other side has a strong incentive to
let the public know.
4.
There are many private side benefits of acquiring political knowledge.
5.
Ex: Investors need to know what government policy will do in order to
pick stocks. When they go to vote,
they can easily rely on information they acquired for quite different reasons.
6.
Voters may just be storing their information in an "inarticulate
format." People often just
take information as it arrives, adjust their conclusion, and then forget the
information, but remember the conclusion. Thus, written tests of political
knowledge don't prove much.
D.
Second,
informed judgments can be made with little information.
1.
Voters have many "cognitive shortcuts." Voters can simply ask their preferred
experts for information.
Application: Just as I don't need to know anything about heart surgery
to get a first-rate bypass operation, I don't need to know anything about
current gun control proposals to vote intelligently about gun control. If I like guns, I just vote the NRA
line; if I don't like guns, I follow the advice of Citizens for Gun Control.
2.
Voters only need to know which of two candidates is closer to their
bliss point; they don't need to know candidates' exact locations.
3.
Analogy between stock markets and elections. Stock markets reflect information well
even though most investors are highly ignorant.
E.
Third,
the deleterious effect of biased information has been overstated.
1.
Remember the Principle of Aggregation? Even if people are highly ignorant,
their random errors will cancel out.
Ignorance does not mean systematic bias.
2.
"To be uninformed about a policy does not imply that voters have
biased estimates of its effects.
For example, to be uninformed about the nature of pork-barrel projects
in other congressional districts does not mean that voters tend to
underestimate the effects of pork barrel - it is quite possible that the
uninformed exaggerate both the extent and the negative consequences of
pork-barrel projects."
3.
Voters can discount, or simply ignore, information from biased or
questionable sources. If the media
has a "liberal bias," then voters can easily adjust. ("Sure,
Koppel said we need more money for the EPA, but what do you expect, he's a big
liberal?")
4.
Worst case: If you "can't trust" the available sources,
don't!
F.
Public choice economists' focus on "rational ignorance," is,
therefore, rather silly. Consumers
and investors are also rationally ignorant about a great deal, but they know enough
for markets to work well.
Similarly, voters know enough for democracy to work well.
G.
Moreover, the Principal of Aggregation assures good outcomes even in
the worst case scenario. (Wittman
even adds that democracy handles severe ignorance better than markets
because aggregation protects the most clueless).
H.
To reach their standard conclusions about political failure, then,
ignorance is not enough. They need
to assume that voters are "stupid" or irrational, something
most economists are extremely unwilling to do.
IV.
How to Think Like Wittman, II: "Serious Lack of Competition"
A.
Many other public choice arguments assume, in Wittman's phrase, a
"serious lack of competition."
B.
While public choice economists spend a great deal of energy studying
political competition, they frequently see strong monopolistic elements as well
(leading to support for things like term limits).
C.
Wittman's Principle #2: Politics,
like the market, is competitive.
D.
Why? First, reputation
matters.
1.
If politicians break promises, voters hold it against them. If they do a good job, they reward
them. Even if politicians only stay
in one office for a few years, they want to build up a good name in order to
rise to higher offices.
2.
Even when politicians plan on leaving politics entirely, their party
rewards them for protecting the party's image.
3.
Parties accordingly "vet" would-be candidates for sincere
ideological commitment.
4.
Remember the theory of optimal punishment: Voters can adjust for a
small probability of detection with over-punishment. Politicians can destroy their whole
reputation with one mistake.
E.
Second,
political races are at least as competitive as markets.
1.
Politics is full of "political entrepreneurs" who want to
stage a successful "takeover" (gain power) by locating unpopular
policies and campaigning to change them.
2.
Incumbent politicians know this, so they strive to preemptively
adjust policy to please the electorate.
3.
High rates of reelection prove NOTHING. "The main reason for high rates of
incumbent success is... They are the best.
That is why they won in the first place and why they are likely to win
again."
4.
Similarity of platforms also proves NOTHING. Similar prices are actually a sign of
competition in markets; so are similar platforms in politics.
5.
Alleged "barriers to entry" are usually minimal. Campaign contributions are just another
sign of a serious candidate. If
contributions were basically bribes to induce politicians to act against voter
interests, political advertising would be counter-productive! Voters would vote against candidates because
they had so much money behind them.
6.
Similarly, third parties can't win because voters don't like them, not
because "the system" is against them.
7.
Ex: The case of Perot shows that it is easy for a third-party candidate
with serious mass support to enter at the highest level.
8.
"Negative" advertising is much more common in elections than
markets. Doesn't this suggest that
elections are actually more competitive?
And there is a simple reason, too: Elections, unlike markets, are
zero-sum games.
9.
Don't forget Tiebout-type competition.
F.
Third,
empirical evidence shows a strong link between voter preferences and
legislative behavior.
G.
Wittman's bottom line: In markets, economists are usually skeptical
about collusion. Why are they less
skeptical in politics? How is the
grand electoral conspiracy maintained?
V.
How to Think Like Wittman, III: "Excessively High
Negotiation/Transfer Costs"
A.
Finally, public choice economists often argue that transactions costs
prevent more efficient policies from replacing the status quo.
1.
Ex: A special interest "blocks" changes harmful to its
interests, and it is "too hard" to buy them off.
B.
This brings us to Wittman's Principle #3: Political bargaining can eliminate any remaining significant
inefficiencies.
C.
Why? Democracy is designed
to have low transactions costs.
1.
Majority rule is cheaper than the unanimity required by markets.
2.
Representative democracy (as opposed to direct democracy) drastically
reduces transactions costs. Instead
of 250 M Americans bargaining, we have a few hundred Congressmen and Senators
bargaining. (The same logic holds
for committees).
3.
Log-rolling can turn efficient but unpopular policies into efficient
AND popular policies.
4.
Long-term political contracts are rarely legally enforceable. But reputation - of both parties and
individual politicians - accomplishes the same thing.
5.
Interest groups also reduce transactions costs by giving legislators
information.
VI.
Asymmetric Information: An Overview
A.
Economists have spent a lot of time thinking about markets with
"asymmetric information."
In essence, this means that some market actors know more than
others about some crucial facts.
B.
Standard example: the "market for lemons." Sellers of used cars know more about the
quality of their car than prospective buyers do.
C.
Naive inference: Sellers "take advantage of buyers."
D.
Sophisticated conclusion: Market price of cars reflects average
car quality. To avoid being taken
advantage of, buyers refuse to make purchases that - on average - aren't
advantageous. Asymmetric
information is therefore also a problem for sellers!
E.
Extreme case: "unraveling." People with the highest-quality used
cars won't sell because they only get the price for an average-quality
car. This lowers average quality
further, reducing the price, leading more high-quality cars to leave... In an extreme case, asymmetric
information can prevent a market from existing at all.
VII.
The Effects of Asymmetric Political Information
A.
Public choice economists have extended asymmetric information models to
politics.
1.
Ex: Pork barrel spending.
Politicians know more about project's social benefits than voters do.
B.
But, Wittman points out, public choice economists frequently leap to
the conclusion that asymmetric information leads to excessive government.
C.
In fact, the truth is the reverse!
Asymmetric information for used cars reduces demand for used cars. Similarly, asymmetric political
information shrinks voters' demand for government.
D.
Why? In both cases,
consumers/voters think "I don't know if this deal is worth it. So I'm going to be more reluctant to
buy."
E.
In other words, voters have a simple way to deal with asymmetric
information: Only vote for programs that are clearly useful. When in doubt, just say no!
F.
Just as it is naive to think that asymmetric information helps used car
dealers sell cars, it is naive to think that asymmetric information helps
politicians create Big Government.
VIII.
Wittman's Sampler, I: Pork Barrel Politics
A.
Pork barrel politics allegedly stem from the geographic nature of
representative. Every Congressman
wants to "bring home the pork" to his district.
B.
Reply #1: Presidents, governments, and other non-geographically-based
politicians often favor larger expenditures than legislatures.
C.
Reply #2: Many programs can be simultaneously abolished with an Omnibus
Repeal Bill (like the base closings bill).
D.
Reply #3: Political parties can take credit for "universal"
policies.
E.
Public choice economists sometimes say that political bargaining fails
because voters won't accept "blatant transfers." (Think of the NJ Turnpike workers).
F.
Reply #4: Wittman calls this knife-edge stupidity. How come voters can recognize efficient
transfers but not inefficient transfers?
IX.
Wittman's Sampler, II: Concentrated Versus Diffuse Interests
A.
Ever since Olson, public choice economists have been impressed by the
ability of interest groups to solve their internal collective action problem in
order to take advantage of the disorganized majority. Standard examples:
1.
Tariffs
2.
Subsidies
3.
Teachers' unions
4.
NRA
B.
Reply #1: Mathematical improbability: Even if politicians lose only a
small fraction of majority's votes, it will rarely be balanced by large
fraction of interest group member's votes.
C.
Reply #2: Interest groups compete with each other, directly or
indirectly.
D.
Reply #3: Competing politicians can advertise their opponents' reliance
on special interest money. ("He took $10 M from the tobacco lobby.")
E.
Reply #4: Politicians realize interest groups are biased, and discount
their advice accordingly.
F.
Reply #5: Special interests win in referenda, too. Ex: Gun control.
G.
Reply #6: Total level of donations is very small, suggesting that
politicians aren't selling much of value.
X.
Wittman's Sampler, III: Bureaucracy
A.
Public choice economists have spent a lot of energy arguing that the
popular suspicions about "bureaucracy" are justified. Bureaucracies supposedly exploit their
monopoly power and voter ignorance to "build empires."
B.
Two variants:
1.
Bureaucracies are inefficient, slow, and directionless. Related complaint:
"satisficing"
2.
Bureaucracies are sophisticated promoters of the interests of
bureaucrats. Related idea:
"budget maximization."
C.
Reply #1: Incremental change is perfectly consistent with maximization
(as opposed to satisficing).
D.
Reply #2: Bureaus compete for funds, so even if they are all
budget-maximizers, it may not matter much.
E.
Reply #3: "Managers" compete to run bureaus, so alleged
monopoly power is really quite limited.
F.
Reply #4: Even if politicians can do what they want because of rational
ignorance, why would politicians charitably "share" this slack with
bureaucrats?
G.
Reply #5: If bureaus really have monopoly power, they will exert it to
get extra pay, not bigger budgets.
(Knife-edge stupidity, again).
H.
Reply #6: Monopoly models predict output is too small, not too large!
I.
Reply #7: If Congress always does what bureaus suggest, this is NOT
evidence of bureaucratic power.
Maybe the bureaus only suggest what they know Congress wants to hear.
J.
Reply #8: Optimal punishment, again. How is the discretion of bureaucrats any
worse than the discretion of lawyers, managers, etc.?
K.
Reply #9: Asymmetric information, again.
XI.
Validity Versus Soundness
A.
Wittman points out that there are four logically possible positions to
take on the efficiency of markets and democracy:
1.
Position #1: Markets fail, democracy works. (View typical of democratic socialists).
2.
Position #2: Markets work,
democracy fails. (View typical of public choice economists).
3.
Position #3: Markets fail, democracy fails. (View typical of hard-line Marxists).
4.
Position #4: Markets work, democracy works. (Wittman's view).
B.
Wittman's goal: End economists' "schizophrenia."
C.
Many public choice economists think that Wittman's arguments are
poor.
D.
But we must keep a basic logical distinction between validity
and soundness firmly in mind.
1.
An argument is valid if it logically follows from its
assumptions.
2.
An argument is sound if it logically follows from its
assumptions AND those assumptions are true.
E.
On the whole, I think Wittman's arguments are usually valid. He is definitely on to something when he
points out other economists' "schizophrenia."
F.
However, I do strongly doubt that many of Wittman's arguments are sound. He reasons carefully from his
assumptions, but rarely considers the possibility that some of these
assumptions are deeply wrong.
G.
Of course, if Wittman's assumptions are wrong but widely-held,
successful critiques of Wittman will probably have wide-ranging ramifications
for public choice (as we will see in the next two weeks).