Prof.
Bryan Caplan
bcaplan@gmu.edu
http://www.bcaplan.com
Econ
854
Week 1: The
Logic of Collective Action
I.
The Many Meanings of Efficiency
A.
The Merriam-Webster College Dictionary defines
"efficiency" as "effective operation as measured by a comparison
of production with cost (as in energy, time, and money)."
B.
Economists occasionally do use "efficiency" in the dictionary
sense - ratio of the value of output to input or something similar.
C.
But normally they use it in quite different ways, and unfortunately
often equivocate between the various uses.
D.
The two most common uses in economics are:
1.
Pareto efficiency
2.
Kaldor-Hicks (or cost-benefit) efficiency
II.
Pareto Efficiency, I
A.
Most of the famous theorems in welfare economics discuss Pareto
efficiency.
B.
A situation is Pareto efficient iff the only way to make one
person better off is to make another person worse off.
C.
Similarly, a Pareto improvement is any change that makes someone
better off without making anyone else worse off.
D.
In theory, it is quite possible that people will voice objections to
Pareto improvements for strategic reasons. So it is not equivalent to a
demonstrated preference standard.
E.
In a highly stylized theoretical setting, Pareto improvements are
conceivable. Ex: If everyone has
identical preferences and endowments.
III.
Pareto Efficiency, II
A.
Even so, there is a strong argument that, in the real world:
1.
Everything is Pareto efficient.
2.
Pareto improvements are impossible.
B.
Why? Almost any change
hurts someone, and it is highly unlikely in practice that literally everyone
can be compensated, that absolutely no one will be missed.
C.
Ex: I buy your watch. How
will we compensate everyone who might have asked you the time?
D.
Rothbard's strange variant: Only count "demonstrated
preferences." Then Pareto
improvements happen all the time.
But especially for an Austrian, this is bizarrely behavioristic.
E.
More fruitful variant: Analyze the Pareto efficiency of ex ante rules
instead of ex post results. (This
is the key intuition behind a lot of constitutional economics). But even then, someone is very likely to
slip through the cracks.
IV.
Kaldor-Hicks Efficiency, I
A.
In practice, then, economists almost always switch to Kaldor-Hicks
efficiency, aka "cost-benefit efficiency."
B.
A situation is Kaldor-Hicks efficient iff the dollar value of
social resources is maximized.
C.
A Kaldor-Hicks improvement is any change than raises the
dollar value of social resources.
D.
Every Kaldor-Hicks efficient situation is Pareto efficient, but most
Pareto efficient situations are NOT Kaldor-Hicks efficient.
E.
Ex: You value a watch at $20, I value it at $30, the strangers you will
encounter value my having the watch at $.10, the (different) strangers I will
encounter value my having the watch at $.10.
1.
If I have the watch, the situation is K-H and Pareto efficient.
2.
If you have the watch, the situation is Pareto but not K-H
efficient. Social value on the
watch rises from $20.10 to $30.10, but your time-askers lose $.10.
F.
Every Pareto improvement is a Kaldor-Hicks improvement, but most
Kaldor-Hicks improvements are not Pareto improvements. (Return to above example).
G.
K-H efficiency is often described as "potentially Pareto
efficient" because if the value of social resources rises, then (assuming
perfect continuity), you could compensate all of the losers by sharing
the gain in surplus.
H.
But what exactly does this "could" mean? Essentially, you could if transactions
costs of arranging compensation were zero.
I.
This bothers many people - why shouldn't the transactions costs count
just as much as other costs?
Ultimately, though, this is just another way of saying that Kaldor-Hicks
improvements don't have to be Pareto improvements. No one said ever said they were.
1.
When you judge whether something is a K-H improvement, you do count the
transactions costs for the move itself.
V.
Kaldor-Hicks Efficiency, II
A.
K-H efficiency naturally gives rise to another concept: deadweight
costs. If the value of social
resources is not maximized, deadweight costs exist.
B.
Everyone knows that you can transfer resources from one person
to another. That's obvious.
C.
Economists' marginal product: It is far less obvious that resources can
be destroyed, leaving no one better off.
D.
Ex: Piracy. It is obvious
that pirates transfer treasure from victims to themselves. The deadweight costs of piracy are far
less obvious. What are they? Treasure that gets lost in the fight,
damage to ships, lost lives on both sides, etc.
1.
The point is not that pirates make themselves worse off by
piracy. At least ex ante, they
don't. The point is that the
pirates only gain a fraction of what the non-pirates lose.
2.
This assumes, of course, that people don't directly enjoy
fighting, watching gold sink to the ocean floor, etc.
E.
Economists often criticize non-economists for thinking in terms of a
"fixed pie" of wealth. In
this sense, economists are more optimistic than the public. However, a corollary is that the pie can
also shrink! In this sense,
economists are more pessimistic than the public. With a fixed pie of resources, conflict
at least has to benefit SOMEONE.
VI.
The Comparative Institutions Approach and "Second Best"
A.
Demsetz famously complained about the "Nirvana fallacy" -
doing (K-H) efficiency comparisons while selectively relaxing important
constraints.
B.
His target was old-style welfare economics, where the solution to any
market shortcoming was government involvement. The shortcomings of government - and
even its basic overhead - were almost never factored in.
C.
Classic example: P>MC.
1.
Standard solution: Impose P=MC price control.
2.
Secondary problem: With fixed costs, firms now lose money.
3.
Standard solution: Subsidize them.
4.
Tertiary problem: How can the subsidies be funded?
5.
Standard solution: Taxes
6.
But what about the DW cost of the taxes?!
7.
And of course this still overlooks a wealth of problems. What is MC? Who awards subsidies, and what are their
incentives? Etc.
D.
Demsetz's lesson is that economists should use a "comparative
institutions approach."
Nothing in the real world is perfectly efficient. What fails least badly?
1.
The Tale of the Emperor
E.
When you add more constraints to a standard problem, the original
optimum is usually no longer feasible.
Economists frequently refer to the original optimum as a
"first-best solution," and the new, worse optimum as a "second-best
solution."
F.
Example: Pricing subject to a P=AC constraint in a decreasing cost
industry.
VII.
Private Versus Social Benefits and Costs
A.
Foundation of welfare economics: realization that private and social
effects can differ.
B.
Ex: A thief clearly enjoys private benefits of stealing. But looking only at the thief's benefits
misses the big picture: The thief makes himself better off by making others
worse off.
C.
Ex: A person driving a
polluting car is better off from driving, but that person isn't the only one
who consumes the exhaust.
1.
Contrast with: Worker safety trade-offs.
D.
How to measure "social benefits"? The same way we always do: willingness
to pay. If some people benefit and
some people suffer from a policy, the net social benefits are the SUM of the
private benefits (positive and negative).
VIII.
Negative Externalities
A.
The basic idea of the tragedy of the commons is that when no one owns a
resource, it gets over-used.
B.
Question: What exactly does "over-use" mean in economic
terms?
C.
Answer: It means that there are costly side effects, or "negative
externalities," that selfish agents don't factor into their
decisions.
D.
How do you diagram negative externalities? In addition to the demand curve, draw a
"social benefits curve."
With negative externalities, the social benefits curve will lie below
the demand curve.
E.
Social optimum is at the intersection of the social benefits curve and
the supply curve, but market equilibrium is at the intersection of the demand
curve and the supply curve.
F.
If the social optimum differs from the market equilibrium, it is
typically called a "market failure."
G.
Negative externalities are also often called "public bads,"
especially when the externalities are large relative to demand (so the socially
optimal quantity is close to zero).
H.
Ex: Pollution. People value
better air, but polluters normally have no incentive to care.
I.
The key: non-excludability.
1.
There is no feasible way to exclude non-payers from the cleaner
air.
2.
Since you do not have to pay
to use it, selfish people will not
pay to use it.
3.
And if no one will pay for it, why would selfish producers provide it?
IX.
Positive Externalities
A.
Positive externalities are the other side of the coin. Positive externalities are beneficial
side effects that selfish agents don't factor into their decisions.
B.
How to diagram? Draw a
social benefits curve above the demand curve.
C.
Positive externalities are also often called "public goods,"
especially when the externalities are large relative to demand (so the
equilibrium quantity is close to zero).
D.
Non-excludability is once again the key. If you can't exclude, there is no
incentive to pay; if there is no incentive to pay, there is no incentive to
produce.
E.
Ex: Defense. People value
defense, but how can suppliers be paid to provide it?
X.
Understanding Externalities
A.
David Friedman's two caveats:
1.
Must distinguish benefits from external benefits. (E.g. education).
2.
Must include both positive and negative externalities in your
calculations. (Important case:
"pecuniary externalities").
B.
Further insight from Friedman: "It is easy to misinterpret
problems of market failure as unfairness rather than inefficiency... The
problem with public goods is not that one person pays for what someone else
gets but that nobody pays and nobody gets, even though the good is worth more that
it would cost to produce."
XI.
Bad but Popular Examples; Good but Unpopular Examples
A.
Some popular and plausible examples:
1.
Air pollution
2.
National defense
3.
Highways and roads (especially local roads)
4.
Law enforcement (especially victimless crimes)
B.
Some popular but dubious examples:
1.
Education
2.
Health and safety
3.
Fire
4.
R&D
C.
Some unpopular but plausible examples (depending on the society):
1.
Censorship
2.
Persecution of religious minorities...
XII.
Fallacies of Group Action
A.
Generalization of public goods theory: People often think in terms of groups
acting to promote their group interests, just as individuals promote
their self-interest.
1.
Workers/capitalists
2.
Women (and men?)
3.
Environment
B.
But this is a fallacy of composition. Just because all members of group X
would benefit if all members did something, it does not follow that it
benefits any individual member to do so.
C.
Ex: Suppose one worker
decides to just stay home and watch TV while the other workers foment
revolution.
1.
Case 1: Revolution succeeds, all workers (supposedly) enjoy a brave new
world - including the couch potato.
2.
Case 2: Revolution fails, all workers continue to suffer under the
capitalist system - but at least the couch potato got to watch some amusing
television programming.
D.
We do need to be careful before we assert that there is no selfish
reason to contribute. Frequently
there are "byproducts" and other "selective incentives"
that make contribution selfishly optimal.
1.
Ex: Trotsky on military discipline
XIII.
Individual Impact: Probability and Magnitude
A.
Saying that "The same thing will happen whatever you
do" is admittedly an overstatement.
More precisely, "About the same thing will probably
happen whatever you do."
B.
In other words, you have to look at the probability you make a
difference and magnitude of that difference, then weigh it against the
cost of acting.
C.
For example, it is possible that if you join the revolution, you will
change the entire course of history.
Possible, but not likely!
D.
More relevant to public choice: the probability a vote matters and the
magnitude of its impact.
E.
Voting increases the probability that your favored candidates wins, but
how much does it increase that probability?
F.
And even if your candidate does win as a result of your vote, how much
will policy change?
XIV.
Calculating the Probability of Decisiveness, I: Mathematics
A.
When does a vote matter? At
least in most systems, it only matters if it "flips" the outcome of
the election.
B.
This can only happen if the winner wins by a single vote. In that case, each voter is "decisive";
if one person decided differently, the outcome would change.
C.
In all other cases, the voter is not decisive; the
outcome would not change if one person decided differently.
D.
It is obvious that the probability of casting the decisive vote in a
large electorate is extremely small.
The 2000 election does not refute this. Losing by 100 or 1000 votes is a long
way from losing by 1 vote!
1.
You might however say that Bush did win by a single vote on the Supreme
Court! But that is an electorate
with only 9 voters.
E.
There is a technical formula for "guesstimating" the
probability of decisiveness using the binomial formula. (Brennan and
Lomasky)
F.
Suppose there are (2n+1) voters asked to vote for or against a policy.
1.
Note: Assuming an odd number of voters avoids the picky problem of
ties.
G.
Then the probability that YOU are the decisive voter is the probability
that exactly n voters out of the 2n voters other than yourself vote
"for."
H.
Now suppose that everyone but yourself votes "for" with
probability p - and "against" with probability (1-p).
I.
Then using the binomial theorem:
J.
From this formula, we can see that the probability of a tie falls when
the number of voters goes up.
Why?
1.
gets smaller as n gets larger
2.
is less or equal to 1. When you raise a number less than 1 to a
larger power, it must get smaller.
K.
This formula also says that as the probability of voter support goes
above or below .5, the probability of a tie falls. Why?
1.
When p=0, ;
when p=1,
too.
In between p=0 and p=1, this term rises to a peak of
when p=.5, then falls.
L.
Intuitively, the more lop-sided opinion on a topic is, the less likely
there is to be a tie. If everyone
agrees, a tie is impossible.
XV.
Calculating the Probability of Decisiveness, II: Examples
A.
Let's work through some examples.
Remember that the number of voters is (2n+1), not n.
B.
Example #1: The close
tenure vote. n=10, p=.5.
, or 17.8%.
C.
Example #2: The close county election. n=5,000, p=.51.
, or a little more than 1-in-1000.
D.
Example #3: The moderately
close county election. n=5000,
p=.53.
, a little less than 1-in-8 billion.
E.
Example #4: The moderately close state election. n=2,000,000, p=.51.
,
a chance smaller than 1 in 10-100! (My calculator just says 0).
F.
Upshot: For virtually any real-world election, the probability of
casting the decisive vote is not just small; it is normally infinitesimal.
The extreme observation that
"You will not affect the outcome of an election by voting" is
true for all practical purposes.
XVI.
Empirical Evidence on Collective Action Problems
A.
One way to get a feel for the logic of collective action is to see how
little participation in politics there is.
Survey of adult Americans from Dye and Zeigler:
Activity |
% |
Run for public office |
<1 |
Active in parties and campaigns |
4-5 |
Make campaign contribution |
10 |
Wear button or bumper sticker |
15 |
Write or call a public official |
17-20 |
Belong to organization |
30-33 |
Talk politics to others |
30-35 |
Vote |
30-55 |
B.
Many experiments have been run to help improve our understanding of
collective action problems.
1.
Part of the design: Rule out "selective incentives" accounts
of apparently unselfish behavior.
C.
Standard design:
1.
I hand out a roll of 100 pennies to each person in the class.
2.
Then, people are allowed to secretly put any number of their pennies
into a jar.
3.
You personally get to keep the pennies you don't put in the jar.
4.
I count the number of pennies in the jar; then I distribute twice
that many pennies to the class, with each person getting the same share.
D.
What maximizes the total income of the class? 100% donation by everyone!
E.
What maximizes your private income (given 3 or more players)? 0% donation!
F.
The first couple of times you do an experiment like this, you typically
get moderate to high levels of donation - 50-80%.
G.
Donation levels usually fall as you repeat the experiment with the same
group. After a while, donation levels
often bottom out at around 20%.
1.
For practical reasons, experiments usually only last a day or
less. So we can still speculate
about what would happen if people played this game 10 times a day for a year.
H.
Donation levels usually decline as the number of participants
rises.
I.
The less secrecy there is, the higher the level of donation.
J.
Conclusion: The "logic of collective action" appears to
exaggerate the degree of human selfishness, but cooperation in these
experiments is still far below the group-income-maximizing level.