A Reply to My Critics At the outset, let me say that I never realized how much effort Mike Huemer must have been putting into replying to his critics over the past year until I found myself compelled to reply to mine. Ive gotten a wealth of responses, and I hope that it will be satisfactory if I reply to what I see as the high points of each of the critiques. Before I begin, I have to say that the portion of my Short Essay with which I was least comfortable was the opening sentence, taking a crack at describing (defining?) the most salient features of free will. My critics, friendly and otherwise, have convinced me that my initial formulation can be seriously improved upon. I present now for your inspection the _two_ formulations between which I am not ready to decide (though I lean towards the second). I think that these will make my thesis clearer and hence more objectionable to the compatibilists than it originally was. First Formulation: A choice is free iff it is caused by a free will. A will is free iff its behavior it not caused (in either the deterministic or probabilistic sense) by anything _whatsoever_. Second Formulation: A choice is free iff it is an activity of a free will. A will is free iff its choices are not caused (in either the deterministic or probabilistic sense) by anything _whatsoever_. If you are having trouble seeing the difference, it is basically the difference between choices being _part of_ the will, vs. something external to but produced by the will. My reason for inclining to the second formulation is basically the introspective one: my choices seem to me to be a veritable piece of my will rather than something external to but produced by my will. In contrast, actions seem external to the will but caused by choices. This said, let me turn to each of my critics in turn. --------------------------------------------------------- To Mike Huemer: 1. I think that my new formulations can handle the definitional problems you raise. 2. With regards to the law of causality, I'm not sure that we are really disagreeing. When C causes A, but you could have prevented C from doing so, we are thinking of "cause" in a looser sense than "is sufficient to produce," since adding an additional factor (the agent's prevention) stops C from causing A. Similarly, I think that there is an ambiguity in the meaning of "ability" in your bicycle example: you are thinking of an ability to do something when circumstances are different (e.g., when the bike has a good cyclist riding it), whereas I am thinking of an ability to do something under exactly the same circumstances. 3. The atom's decay. I must admit that I keep having the determinist in mind as my foil, but of course the probabilist is just as contrary. So let me further clarify. When I say (as in my second formulation) that the will is not caused by anything whatsoever, I have in mind not only deterministic causation, but also causality according to the pattern of any probability distribution. Of course, ex post there will always be an empirical histogram of what _has_been_chosen; but I deny that ex ante the will's behavior is caused to behave according to any probability density function. 4. I didn't mean to quote your comment that "Judgment is something ones does, whereas having a feeling is something that happens to one." Rather it _inspired_ my own claim, even though they are about different subject matters. Sorry if you felt mis-quoted. 5. My thought experiment. Well, I hate to start lecturing one of the world's experts of thought experiments about thought experiments, but... Your objection that we couldn't "measure the initial conditions" just seems to me to totally miss the point. For I could just as easily have said: suppose the scientists have these equations, and suppose they can measure the initial conditions perfectly. NOW would you be able to falsify their predictions? And of course you could. And SINCE YOU COULD DO IT IN THIS HYPOTHETICAL CASE (as you must admit), I conclude that we actually DO have free will in the real world. Why? Well, you could only falsify the equations in the thought experiment if you have free will in the real world. And you see via the experiment that you could falsify them; hence in the real world, not just the imaginary case, you have free will. ------------------------------------------------------------ To Brock Sides: 1. The Failure of Compatibilism I hope that my revised definition distinguishes our views to your satisfaction. That said, I have to say that I find your position to be highly implausible. As you put it, "attributions of ability, such as 'could have done otherwise', are context-dependent modal attributions." So when we say that I am free to choose what to drink, we make this statement in "a looser context than one which considers all the laws of physics." It is true if we ignore some of the knowledge of the world which we have. Now the biggest problem with your view is this: on your definition of "freedom," even a ROCK has freedom. If we talk in a looser context than one which considers all of the laws of physics, a rock might suddenly explode or fly off into space. A plant, if we talk in the "looser context," might grow on the ground or crawl up onto the wall. Are we to conclude that plants and rocks are free? Well, they do have freedom in the compatibilist sense; in which case, I suggest, the compatibilists' "freedom" is just a distortion of language. Searle puts it more eloquently than I could: "The problem about compatibilism, then, is that it doesn't answer the question, 'Could we have done otherwise, all other conditions remaining the same?', in a way that is consistent with our belief in our own free will. Compatibilism denies the substance of free will while maintaining its verbal shell." (_Minds, Brains, and Science_, p.89) A final point to make about compatibilism is that it doesn't say anything that hard-core determinists would disagree with, but it sure does say things which the advocate of "libertarian" free will would disagree with. It isn't even a position distinct from determinism, but rather a vain attempt to make the implausibilities of determinism a little easier to swallow. 2. My Four Arguments and Compatibilism I just don't see how any of my four arguments could support compatibilism. Let's go through the three you think do. A. Observation. Well, if I observe "libertarian" free will through introspection, then obviously there is a contradiction between (A) and compatibilism. "Begs the question!" you say? All I can ask the reader to do is introspect further. Do you observe your will to be free "in a looser context than one which considers all the laws of physics"? Or do you observe yourself to be free in reality, taking any knowledge of science or philosophy into account? C. Initial plausibility. Again, I think that before you studied philosophy, you would have said that it is very plausible that your will is actually free in the hard-core sense. And if that premise exceeds the probability of any of your subsequent studies conflicting with this view, then my argument works. D. The Thought Experiment. How in the world is this consistent with compatibilism? I explicitly take the context of all the laws of physics into the structure of the thought experiment, and then argue that you could still do otherwise. To agree with me in this thought experiment is to say that _whatever context we consider_ we are free, not just free if we disregard about some of what we know. 3. The Reductio Ad Absurdum to Skepticism. Well, to begin with, free will does not lead to skepticism, because we can _choose_ to believe things because they are true. (Nice point, though.) And of course dualism and determinism are theoretically compatible. I'm not sure if you've gotten my basic point that under the determinist assumption, our true beliefs are the result of irrational forces. (Unless you are a determinist who believes that Truth itself is an active causal force in the world, alongside matter/energy and genes/environment. Any takers?) In any case, this is my least favorite argument of the four, though I am sure Mike Huemer would be happy to defend it more extensively than myself. :-) ------------------------------------------------------------------ To Alan Eaton: You've made me a little more aware of the need to confront the probabilist along with the determinist; hopefully my new formulations make you happy in that respect. 1. The Argument from Science. I agree with your claim that "any discoveries or claims should be able to be rationalised against the vast body of scientific knowledge that already exists." However, I also think that any purported scientific knowledge must be rationalized against the vast body of common sense and philosophic truth which already exists. My rationalization, if you haven't guessed it, is pretty simple: the scientific claims you have in mind have only been verified with regards to inanimate matter with any precision; whereas the common sense and philosophical claim that free will exists has been verified for human beings for as long as people have had either common sense or philosophy. I claim that I witness the experimental falsification of whatever scientific laws you have in mind every time I lift my arm. Of course, this falsification merely _sets limits to_ the applicability of these scientific laws rather than refuting them. Why is this so hard to swallow? After all, the point of science is to explain our observations, not to systematically discredit some empirical observations at the expense of others. 2. Contra Observation. I am still unclear as to what your basis for discounting introspective knowledge is. Apparently, it contradicts scientific findings. But those scientific findings are based on...extrospective observations (such as what we see). So despite your appeal to the authority of science, you don't see to be doing anything other than choosing some kinds of observations over others. I am trying to explain how all of our observations, extrospective and introspective alike, can be valid, which strikes me as satisfying the true empirical spirit of the sciences. As for your claim that introspection is turned in on itself, the same could be said of any we study the eye by looking at it, etc. Your final remarks seem to bely your claim that you aren't systematically favoring some senses over others: "And what if our mental freedom consistently returns false information?" And what if X consistently returns false information, where X is wherever you think you are getting your information? To appeal to "science" on this one would, in Hume's words, "Evidently be going in a circle, and taking for granted the very point in question." 3. My Reductio. You basically seem to accepted my reductio to skepticism. "Determinism might imply skepticism (and it certainly does) [!!! - BC] but it does not imply that we _know_ that skepticism is true." Hold on here. If we know determinism as true (you more or less do, I'm not sure if you have probabilistic or regular determinism in mind), and we know (as we certainly do [?]) that determinism implies skepticism, then why don't we know that skepticism is true? We seem forced to that conclusion. Which is absurd, because the conclusion contradicts the premise. As far as I can tell, you've admitted everything needed for the reductio to work, but then just refuse to reject the premises and accept free will. I'm honestly puzzled. 4. My Thought Experiment. You seem to make the same mistake that I accuse Mike of. This is a thought experiment. The premises don't need to be true to yield an interesting conclusion. John Searle doesn't really be able to memorize Chinese manuals for the Chinese room argument to work; nor does Einstein's train need to be able to travel at the speed of light. So to your allusions to Chaos theory, I just say: OK, run the same thought experiment, assuming that the scientists have figured out how to surmount any difficulties raised by Chaos theory so their predictions are perfect. 5. The Propriety of Bringing Up Consequences. Of course, bringing up "some unsavoury implications" does not refute a view. That's why I left it for the end. After having refuted a view, it seems perfectly reasonable to point out the damage caused by the alternative view, in order to motivate and inspire people to actively crusade against the view after they have rationally changed their minds. Moreover, bringing up unsavoury implications has an added bonus: if the proponents of determinism want to be consistent, they must accept all of the unsavoury implications or abandon determinism (or be irrational). Since they rarely do accept the unsavoury implications, I think it suggests that they are more in inner doubt that they will admit. ---------------------------------------------------- To William Adlam: 1. The Argument from Science, revisited. You have a whole section premised on "Every physical event is governed by the laws of physics." Obviously, it is child's play to get out of this. Either an event involving mental-physical interaction is not "physical," or else the law is false. What is supposed to be so plausible about this law, anyway? It just sounds good until we think about mind-body interaction, when it just breaks down. 2. Do We Choose Beliefs? This is a point more about my specific version of free will, which I am only too happy to move the discussion towards. Let's take your example: "There are several occasions when, if I had been able to, I would have chosen to believe that I would never die." But hold there are _lots_ of people who have chosen to believe this. People who have the same knowledge of science etc. as yourself. How do they do it? Probably by consciously ignoring the implications of their other views. If you have any doubt about the ability to choose beliefs, just look at what crazy beliefs some people have. The evidence isn't breaking their mental door down. Now I'll admit that it would be _difficult_ to belief some things. But I think that they are difficult in the sense I mentioned: it is difficult for someone who has developed virtuous mental habits to cast them aside in favor of illusory but pleasant hopes. Just as it would be difficult to murder a loved one or do anything else you think is wrong. It is difficult to do because your emotions militate against it, not because a steely exercise of will could not accomplish it. 3. Observing Uncausedness. I just have to say that I positively observe uncausedness in my choices. I bet most other people do as well. It isn't like finding a murder victim and then saying, "Hmm. I wonder what caused it." We experience our choices as positively uncaused, rather than merely as difficult to identify the cause. 4. The Thought Experiment. Again, I reiterate that a thought experiment need not have true premises to yield interesting conclusions. It doesn't matter if a train can really travel at the speed of light. Similarly, it doesn't matter if there could be a "negative feedback loop." Just run the same thought experiment, plus add the stipulation that the scientists' equation eventually converges. Even then, I could still refute it. ------------------------------------------------------ To Tom Clark: Well, I don't disagree with much of what you say, because you mainly seem to be point out the practical problems with living consistently with the determinist conclusion. All I can say is that I would be very surprised indeed if ordinary people suddenly dropped all of the talk of free will and started looking at e.g. criminals as helpless puppets. It is also unclear to me why, on your own view, we "ought" to give up these allegedly false ways of evaluating behavior in favor of the "scientific" model. Maybe we are helplessly determined to be unscientific. (Searle sure seems to think he is.) What comes to mind is an old cartoon of a judge pronouncing sentence: "I realize that you committed these crimes because of your background. What I want you to realize is that my background is making me sentence you to twenty years of hard labor." ----------------------------------------------------------- To Ben Fischer: Yep, you are basically right. I am a hard-core dualist. And since I think that mental things cause physical things (which even the determinist dualist might think), I guess that makes me an "interactionist." Does that help? From lsanger@magnus.acs.ohio-state.edu Sat Feb 4 10:24:03 1995 Received: from bottom.magnus.acs.ohio-state.edu by ponyexpress.princeton.edu (8.6.9/1.7/newPE) id KAA06810; Sat, 4 Feb 1995 10:24:02 -0500 Received: from [128.146.24.95] by bottom.magnus.acs.ohio-state.edu (8.6.4/4.940426) id KAA08646; Sat, 4 Feb 1995 10:21:18 -0500 Date: Sat, 4 Feb 1995 10:21:18 -0500 Message-Id: <199502041521.KAA08646@bottom.magnus.acs.ohio-state.edu> To: (Recipient list suppressed) From: lsanger@magnus.acs.ohio-state.edu (ASP-Disc) Subject: belated reply to Caplan (part 1) Status: RO From: "Paul V. Torek" Part 1 of my reply to Bryan Caplan on free will. Since it's a pain to insert a ">" before each line, I'll just put three ---'s above, and three below, each quotation. Starting here. --- At the outset, it is necessary to gt a clear understanding of what exactly "free will" is. A being has free will if given all other causal factors in the universe (genetic and environmental, physical and chemical are two popular current pairings) it nevertheless possesses the ability to choose more than one thing. --- Bryan's definition has incompatibilism built-in. I will argue that this is an error. (In later posts Bryan revised his definition slightly, but not in respects relevant to the criticism I'll make.) Free will is real. But this does not mean that we are not fully integral parts of the causal network of nature. There is no conflict between the acknowledgement that a person acts freely and the claim that her acts are a result of causal chains that stretch back far before her birth. --- I observe uncaused changes during my every waking moment, whenever I contemplate my own choices. --- When I contemplate my choices, I see that it is *up to me* whether I shall do one thing or another. But this is different from seeing that my choices are *uncaused*: that is an interpretation, and a bad one, of the phenomenon of choice. --- My second argument consists in a reductio ab absurdum. I shall begin with the assumption of determinism, and show that it leads to the self-contradictory position of abject skepticism. [... deletia ...] point is that my views -- correct and incorrect alike -- would be the result of inexorable causal forces. And these forces determine people to error just as inexorably as they determine them to truth. Of course, I might be correct by coincidence. --- Or you might be correct by skill. There are good evolutionary reasons why organisms like human beings could be expected to be good at tracking the truth. And if a being is good at tracking the truth, is sensitive to evidence, etc., how much more justification can you possibly want? As readers of one list already know, I hold "externalist" views in the theory of knowledge. Basically that just means that the paradigm of knowledge, for me, is the cognitive state of a being who uses reliable truth-tracking methods and gets true beliefs as a result. (I'll delete some further argument concerning "bottom-up explanantions" and "micro-particles", because I've already replied to Mike Huemer's version of that argument.) [to be continued] --Paul Torek, flink@elf.bsdi.com