Bryan Caplan Koch Fellows Program Essay #2 "One of the great tragedies of human history - and the central tragedy of Christianity - is the break-up of the harmonious world- order which had evolved, in the Dark Ages, on a Christian basis. Men had agreed, or at least had appeared to agreee, on an all-enveloping theory of society which not only aligned virtue with law and practice, but allotted to everyone in it precise, Christian-oriented tasks. There need be no arguments or divisions because everyone endorsed the principles on which the system was run. They had to. Membership of the society, and the acceptance of its rules, was ensured by baptism, which was compulsory and irrevocable. The unbaptized, that it the Jews, were not members of the society at all; their lives were spared but otherwise they had no rights. Those who, in effect, renounced their baptism by infidelity or heresy, were killed. For the remainder, there was total agreement and total commitment. The points on which men argued were slender, compared to the huge areas of complete acquiescence which embraced almost every aspect of their lives." --Paul Johnson, A History of Christianity Otto Gierke's Political Theories of the Middle Ages 1. Gierke on the Antique, the Medieval, and the Modern The underlying theme of Gierke's history of medieval thought goes like this: the ancient world, mainly of Greece and Rome, developed a distinctive political tradition. The content of this tradition is not too clear; but its flavor was individualistic and pluralistic. It contained republican ideas like popular sovereignty and representation, and opposition to tyranny. Moreover, it contained the seeds of natural law theory -- roughly, the idea that some acts are right or wrong independent of what state authorities say, which thereby constrains the legitimate behavior of government. Now during medieval times, a startling different philosophy appeared, inspired by the universal cultural takeover of the Catholic Church. Gierke argues that the chief feature of this "medieval" philosophy was an organic philosophy of the relationship between society, the state, and the church. To be more precise, distinctively medieval thinkers did not see society as a collection of individuals pursuing their several aims. (This is what Gierke somewhat incorrectly calls the "atomistic" and "mechanistic" theory of society.) Rather they thought of the ruled as the body of society, and the authorities as the head. Of course, the head does the thinking and figures out what the body is going to do -- and the body goes along. This model lends itself to a total society, since there is only one group that does the serious thinking and other people are supposed to obey rather than work out their own views. Complicating this matter is the fact that medieval society contained two rival heads. As Gierke humorously suggests, the idea of a two-headed body was hard for medievals to bear: "were the Emperor an additional Head of this Mystical Body, we should have before us a two-headed monster, an animal biceps." (p.22) For a long while, this metaphor was resolved in favor of the Church. The Pope's supporters developed the two-swords theory, arguing that the Pope ruled the religious realm directly and the secular one indirectly. Monarchs were merely appointed servants of the Pope, who granted them their power, limited it, and could take it away if it were abused. Monarchs preferred another theory that gave them wider scope: rather than thinking of the mnonarch as subordinate to the Church, it would be better to think of the Church as the spirit of society and the secular government as the body. This formally conceded the superiority of the Church (since the soul is nobler than the body) but left day-to-day power in the practical world in the hands of the monarch. Having alluded to ancient and sketched medieval political thought, Gierke then presents his most bold and challenging thesis. He argues that when medieval thinkers re-introduced their time to ancient political thought, they inadvertently destroyed their own distinctive political tradition. Modern thought is based largely on ancient thought; the history of medieval thought may be seen as the slow resurrection in a new historical context of the concepts and principles of the ancient world. As Gierke explains, "If from the point at which we have placed ourselves we survey the Political Doctrine of the Middle Age, we see within the medieval husk an 'antique-modern' kernel. Always waxing, it draws away all vital nutriment from the shell, and in the end that shell is broken. Thus the history of the Political Theories of the Middle Age is at one and the same time a history of the theoretical formulation of the System of Medieval Society and the history of the erection of that newer edifice which was built upon a foundation of Natural Law." (pp.4-5) 2. The Limits of Power: Popular Sovereignty, Representation, and Natural Law Unfortunately, most of Gierke's historical support lies in foreign-language footnotes which I cannot fairly evaluate. But apparently he believes that the medievals picked up several anti- authoritarian ideas from ancient authors. First, there is the idea of popular sovereignty. In ancient times, many people thought that the Roman people, taken as a whole, had some say in their government. This is not to imply that they actually got to participate or even should get to participate; but it makes the government into a sort of servant of the nation rather than the master. And under dire circumstances, authority might revert or "escheat" to the people. As first this doctrine had no practical application in the Catholic Church: "The Church, it is true, avoided this conclusion by the supposition that, since the advent of Christ, the rights of the People had passed to Him and from Him to Peter and Peter's successors." (p.40) But this strange interpretation had many rivals who argued that popular sovereignty limited even the power of the Church. The idea spread that in the event of papal heresy, the Pope could be judged by the Whole Church and replaced. The idea of representation also took root. Curiously, many people saw the monarch as a kind of representative of the people, whose power was in some sense a temporary grant. Citizens' assemblies formed in many towns and cities, whose obligation it was to represent the interests of all. Cardinals, Electors in the Holy Roman Empire, and the Pope himself were worked into theories of representation. Whether this theory actually limits government power is another matter; perhaps it moderately constrained serious abuses. The most powerful idea that the medievals borrowed from the ancient world was that of natural law. Now Christian thinkers had always recognized that God's law was superior to man's; but natural law theorists added a new check upon authority. They distinguished between the eternal and universal standards that God gives us in revelation, and the equally eternal and universal standards that we know by reason alone. "The revealed Law of God stood to the Law of Nature (properly so-called) in this relation, namely, that while the latter was implanted by God in Natural Reason for the attainment of earthly ends, the former was communicated by God to man in a supernatural way and for a supramundane purpose." (pp.75-76) Any positive law contrary to either the Law of God or the Law of Nature was usually held to be void. Of course, the doctrine of natural law could be used to enforce state power rather than check it. Perhaps natural law requires us to kill heretics. But in practice, Gierke thinks that it was mainly a check on rather than a mandate for state action. 3. Conclusion: Extending Gierke I confess a prior sympathy for Gierke's rough outline of history, and want to suggest a broader and blunter application of his ideas. Namely: The origins of individualism and liberty lie in the Graeco-Roman world, whereas the origins of collectivism and totalitarianism lie in Christianity. If Gierke is right that the good aspects of the modern world arose because ancient ideas infiltrated Christian civilization, how might we explain the totalitarian horrors of the modern world? The most plausible hypothesis is that modern totalitarianism draws its inspiration from the totalitarianism of the Middle Ages. Just as the Enlightenment emerged when ancient ideas replaced medieval ones, so too did totalitarianism emerge when medieval ideas replaced those of the Enlightenment. In so short a space, I cannot begin to prove this here; but I think that Paul Johnson's Modern Times and A History of Christianity inadvertently make a rather strong case.