Prof.
Bryan Caplan
bcaplan@gmu.edu
http://www.bcaplan.com
Econ
812
Week 2:
General Equilibrium
I.
Strategic Interaction Between Maximizers
A.
Economists usually think of individual agents as maximizing something,
but rarely analyze individuals in isolation. For social scientists, interesting
questions almost always involve more than one individual.
B.
Such interesting questions are however analytically challenging. When one person "plays against
nature," the action is one-sided.
You do not need to worry about how your "opponent" will change
its behavior in response to your behavior.
Once there is more than one person, you do.
1.
Even this is oversimplified, since animals can play strategically to
some degree. But no one e.g.
expects wolves and rabbits to form an alliance against hunters.
C.
Given the complexity of the problem, economists have focused a lot of
time on a very easy case. Imagine
that there are not just more than one agent, but a lot of agents. So many, in fact, that you do not have
to worry about how other actors will strategically respond to your decisions.
1.
There are many examples of this kind of thinking. When you buy corn, you do not
contemplate how corn farmers will respond to your purchase.
D.
Interesting result: Once you make the problem easy in this one way, you
can make it extremely complex in other ways, and still get clear answers. Analysis of complex economies from this
starting point is known as general equilibrium theory.
II.
Examples of General Equilibrium
A.
Simple example: Suppose I consumers have identical preferences
and endowments in a two-good economy.
U=a ln x + b ln y; a+b=1.
These agents make exchanges in markets where they know their personal
behavior has no perceptible effect on prices.
B.
What happens? Intuitively,
this situation is sustainable only if prices induce everyone to consume their
own endowment!
C.
Formally: We can substitute out for y by noting that , and in a
commodity economy,
, so agents maximize:
D.
Differentiating, we learn that: . Since agents
consume all of their income:
,
, the usual constant-income-fractions result.
E.
Now simply find the prices that induce everyone to consume their initial
endowments. Set ,
. Then you have
. Simplifying, we
learn that:
. The equilibrium
price of x is directly proportional to the taste parameter for x and the
initial endowment of y; the price of y is directly proportion to the taste
parameter for y and the initial endowment of x.
F.
What if we make things more interesting by allowing for taste and
endowment differences?
Specifically, each agent i has Ui=ai ln x +
bi ln y, and endowments and
. Then what?
G.
Now agents are actually going to make trades at equilibrium prices,
instead of just noting that prices leave no incentive to trade. So we have to find the prices that
induce aggregate consumption to equal aggregate endowments, taking the full
interaction between prices and consumption into account.
H.
Formally, add up I equations for individual consumption of x as
a function of prices and initial endowments. Then impose the constraint that . This gives us:
. Solving, we
find that:
. Once again, we
have solved for prices as a function of preferences and initial endowments.
1.
Note: We would get the same result if we solved for y instead. Intuitively, if there are two markets
and one clears, so does the other.
I.
Worth noticing: Utility function implies that people will give up
anything to have a finite quantity of each good. If half of the people had no x, and the
rest had both, why couldn't the no-x-ers be induced to give up practically all
of their y?
III.
General Equilibrium in Pure Exchange Economies
A.
General equilibrium problems can be analyzed in very general terms.
B.
Formally, assume:
1.
There are I consumers indexed i=1,...,I.
2.
There are K commodities indexed k=1,...,K.
3.
Commodity consumption must be non-negative.
4.
Utility Ui(x) is strictly increasing in
all commodities (stronger than necessary, but simpler).
5.
Consumers start with endowments of commodities; endowment of consumer i
is ei.
6.
There is a continuous market price vector p=(p1,...,pk)
that agents treat as exogenous.
C.
Then let us define general equilibrium to be a situation in
which:
1.
Consumer i maximizes Ui s.t. px£
2.
Aggregate consumption never exceeds aggregate endowments: .
D.
Intuition: Since endowments and utility functions are fixed, what
varies to make an equilibrium possible?
The consumption vectors, x.
And what changes consumption vectors? Naturally, the price vector, p.
IV.
Sufficient Conditions for Existence of General Equilibrium
A.
Caveat: General equilibrium might still exist even though sufficient
conditions not met!
B.
First, note that the inequalities can be replaced with equalities
because utility functions are strictly increasing.
C.
Second, note that since this is an endowment economy, multiplying all
prices through by a scalar l changes nothing; if p
is an equilibrium price vector, so is lp. So we can restrict attention to price
equilibria where .
D.
Then the following assumptions guarantee the existence of general
equilibrium.
E.
Assumption 1: Ui(p) has a unique solution for all i
and all p.
F.
Assumption 2: Total demand for good k exceeds total endowment
for a small enough pk, and falls short of total endowment for
a large enough pk.
G.
Assumption 3: The total demand function for k is continuous in pk
for 0<pk<1.
H.
In a 2-commodity world (k=2), you can prove the existence of
general equilibrium using the Intermediate Value Theorem. If one market clears, the other has to
clear, and if demand is continuous and can be too high or too low, it must at
some point be just right.
I.
In a k-commodity world, you can prove the existence of general
equilibrium using Brouwer's Fixed Point Theorem. Basic idea of fixed point theorems: find
conditions for functions such that there must be an f(x)=x. All of our assumptions together
conveniently satisfy Brouwer's Fixed Point Theorem, so QED.
J.
How do you get to these fixed points? GE theory usually focuses on the
"Walrasian auctioneer" who adjusts price vectors to eliminate excess
demands. (Austrians tend to hate
this). We will discuss alternatives
later.
V.
Counter-Examples
A.
When would a general equilibrium not exist? Each of the assumptions is made for a
reason. Some of the more notable
possible reasons for non-existence:
B.
Counter-example #1: Lexiocographic preferences, hence no utility
function. No prices would induce
people to give up the lexicographically preferred commodity.
C.
Counter-example #2: Discontinuity.
If total demand for x is 90% of endowment at p=.7, and 110% of endowment
at p=.7-e.
D.
Counter-example #3: Demand not "well-behaved" at extreme
prices. This might simply imply 0
prices for some goods, but there may be technical complications.
E.
Counter-example #4: Prices are discontinuous. If prices have to be in discrete 1-penny
units, for example, general equilibrium may not exist.
F.
Remember: Standard theorems give sufficient conditions. G.E. might exist anyway. Ex: Linear utility functions, where
U=x+y. What assumption does this
violate? Can you describe the G.E.
anyway? (Hint: What happens to
demand for x if the price of x exceeds the price of y? Vice versa?)
VI.
The Two Welfare Theorems
A.
Market-clearing prices in individual markets have familiar welfare
properties. At the intersection of
S&D, total surplus is maximized, so the allocation must be Pareto
efficient.
B.
But can these results be generalized to multiple markets? General equilibrium theory can prove
that the results from simple S&D cases generalize broadly.
C.
First Welfare Theorem: Under the previous assumptions, the general
equilibrium allocation is Pareto efficient.
D.
There is a standard proof by contradiction. Suppose that x is an equilibrium
allocation but x' is Pareto superior to x.
1.
Then since x' must be feasible, .
2.
Then since prices are non-negative, .
3.
Since utility is strictly increasing in consumption, .
4.
This implies that .
5.
BUT: By the definition of Pareto improvement, all consumers must weakly
prefer x' to x, one must strictly prefer x' to x. Weak preference requires that x' not be more
affordable than x: . Strict
preference requires that x' be not affordable for some i, so for at
least one person,
.
6.
Summing up these weak and strong inequalities implies that: , contradicting (4).
E.
Many economists find this welfare theorem less than compelling. After all, an allocation where one
person owned everything is also Pareto efficient. But these economists often find hope in
the second main result (some additional assumptions on utility functions are
needed, and I omit the proof):
F.
Second Welfare Theorem: Any Pareto efficient allocation can be a general
equilibrium given some initial endowments.
G.
Standard interpretation: Just by changing initial endowments
("redistributing") in the right way, you can make any Pareto
efficient allocation self-sustaining.
H.
Philosophical perspective: All distributive complaints against
competitive markets can be answered with some form of lump-sum
redistribution. Mere existence of
the market does not make any efficient equilibrium unsustainable.
I.
Possible contrast: Democracy.
VII.
Arrow-Debreu Contingent Claims Markets
A.
General equilibrium already seems rather general. But Arrow and Debreu noticed that it was
much more general than anyone realized.
B.
G.E. can handle intertemporal markets. Just think of good k at time t
as a different good than k at time t+1. Instead of trading current goods, you
can trade promises to deliver goods at any time.
C.
Ex: I have an endowment of bananas in 2016 that I can trade just as if
there were physical bananas in my hands.
D.
More impressively, G.E. can handle an arbitrary level of
uncertainty. Just think of good k
if x happens to be a different good than k if not-x happens.
E.
Ex: I have an endowment of bananas in 2016 if average
temperature exceeded 80 degrees. I
can trade this contingent claim just like I had some physical bananas right
now.
1.
Imagine taking an unconditional claim and ripping it into pieces, each
of which specifies the conditions under which it pays off.
F.
In both cases, the problem is isomorphic to the standard one, so all of
the standard results go through.
G.
Natural extension: Betting markets.
H.
Particularly interesting: You can analyze contingent claims markets
without specifically talking about time preference or probabilities.
VIII.
Application: Intertemporal Consumption
A.
Macroeconomists often analyze consumption over time. How can you move from individual (or
small country) analysis to general equilibrium?
B.
Once again, the trick is to find the prices that induce aggregate
consumption to equal aggregate endowments.
In intertemporal markets, such prices are usual known as interest rates.
C.
So suppose the world is populated by identical infinitely-lived agents
who maximize , and have a given endowment stream.
D.
Standard result is that each individual sets . If
,
you consume less every period; if
,
you consume more every period.
E.
But what happens in general equilibrium? In general equilibrium, consumption must
equal endowments in every period.
Therefore, if endowments are constant and people have identical preferences,
.
F.
Similarly, if endowments are growing at a rate (1+g), people want
to smooth consumption by borrowing against their future income. So interest rates in general equilibrium
must rise high enough that people are content consuming their current endowment
and no more. This happens when . Expected growth raises interest rates
today!