Prof.
Bryan Caplan
bcaplan@gmu.edu
http://www.bcaplan.com
Econ
854
I.
Return to the "Miracle of Aggregation"
A.
The leading explanation for democratic failure is voters’
rational ignorance.
B.
There can be little doubt that voters are highly ignorant.
C.
But as discussed earlier, many assert that voter ignorance is quite
compatible with well-functioning democracy!
D.
Why? If we interpret
"ignorance" as "random error," then the Principle of
Aggregation kicks in. If you
tabulate millions of random errors and take an average, the aggregate acts
"as if" it were fully informed.
That is the Miracle of Aggregation.
E.
So far, so good. But why
should we believe that voters' errors ARE random in the first place?
A.
There are two distinct ways economists apply the concept of
“rationality”:
1.
Rationality of action
2.
Rationality of belief
B.
In the last thirty years, rational expectations has been a standard
technique for modeling economic actors’ beliefs. Economists often refer to
“rationality” and “rational expectations”
interchangeably.
C.
Key feature of RE: calibration.
RE requires some connection, albeit imperfect, between agents’
beliefs and the real world.
D.
RE partitions error between:
1.
Irrationality - the systematic component
2.
Ignorance - the random component
E.
RE then rules out the first type of error. Non-random errors ipso facto become
evidence of "irrationality."
F.
But merely defining systematic errors as "irrational" is hardly
evidence that they don't exist on a wide scale. Maybe RE is false, and in that sense,
people are not rational. It is an
empirical question.
G.
There are weaker definitions of rationality that allow mere ignorance
to co-exist with systematic error.
1.
Bayesian rationality, for example, merely demands that people update
their beliefs in a certain way, but puts no constraints on their priors. These may be wildly unrealistic.
H.
A still weaker sense of rationality: truth-seeking. However deluded they are, agents qualify
as long as they want to have true
beliefs.
I.
These weaker senses of irrationality still have some connection to systematic error. If you do not update your beliefs
conditional on evidence, or if you do not care about truth, you are more likely
to have wildly unrealistic views.
J.
If you switch to a non-RE definition, you can save
“rationality,” but rationality is no longer enough to make
democracy work.
K.
In practice, most economists do equate “rationality” with
RE, so I will stick with this definition throughout the lecture.
III.
Rational Ignorance Versus Rational Irrationality
A.
What reason is there to believe that the rational expectations
assumption is true?
B.
The main argument is that systematic errors are costly, so people try to:
1.
Avoid them in the first place.
2.
Learn from the systematic mistakes they do happen to make.
C.
Big problem here: Some systematic errors are less costly than others,
and some can hardly be called costly at all.
D.
One of my main ideas: Just as economists think of agents weighing the
costs and benefits of information, so
too can we think of agents weighing the costs and benefits of rationality. Just as it is sometimes rational to be ignorant (have little information), it
may sometimes be rational to be irrational
(deviate from full rationality).
1.
Psychological interpretation?
E.
In other words, we can think of irrationality as a normal good. Why does anyone want this
"good"?
1.
Big reason: People derive comfort, security, and sense of identity from
their belief structure – and rational thinking is often hard, painful,
discouraging work.
2.
Indirect reason: Other people you depend on may treat you differently
depending on your beliefs.
3.
For more: See Mosca, The Ruling
Class, chapter 7 (on the syllabus)
F.
What is the "price" of irrationality? It is the material success that you give
up in order to retain systematically mistaken beliefs.
G.
Writing down an individual's "demand for irrationality" curve
for a given issue is easy. Just put
quantity of irrationality on the x-axis, and the implicit price of irrationality
on the y-axis.
1.
Neoclassical demand for irrationality
2.
Near-neoclassical demand for irrationality
H.
When the price of irrationality is high - as it often will be - people
consume less. Perhaps they consume
none at all - on at least some issues, they might be fully rational.
I.
When the price of irrationality is low, people consume more. When irrationality is completely free,
people stick with whatever belief makes them most happy, however crazy.
J.
Remember our old friend, the probability of voter decisiveness?
K.
Immediate implication: The expected price of voter irrationality is
essentially zero, so we should not be surprised if voters hold highly
irrational beliefs!
L.
Question: How is this different from expressive voting?
M.
Answer: Expressive voting says that people don't really care if policies work. Rational irrationality says people
believe their favored policies do
work, but have irrational beliefs about what works!
1.
Ex: The public reaction to WWI.
V.
Systematically Biased Beliefs About Economics
A.
There are many subject matters where irrational beliefs may lead to
inefficient policy.
B.
But one subject matter that seems especially interesting for public
choice is economics itself.
1.
Most policy decisions of modern government have significant economic
content.
2.
Economists have written about economic misconceptions for hundreds of
years - most famously, French economist Frederic Bastiat.
C.
I have done a lot of empirical work on this topic; chapter 3 of The Myth of the Rational Voter
summarizes it.
1.
Data: the Survey of Americans and
Economists on the Economy (SAEE).
1510 members of the general public, 250 Ph.D. economists.
D.
Standard method of testing for irrationality: Look for differences in
mean beliefs of laypeople and experts.
E.
Complication: Critics of economists claim that it is the economists who
are biased rather than the public!
1.
Self-serving bias
2.
Ideological bias
F.
In my empirical work, however, I am able to show that large systematic
belief differences persist controlling
for self-serving and ideological bias.
[Tables]
G.
What main clusters of systematic belief differences emerge?
1.
Anti-market bias
2.
Anti-foreign bias
3.
Make-work bias
4.
Pessimistic bias
H.
What kinds of inefficient policies could each of these four categories
explain?
1.
Education
2.
Being male
3.
Job security
4.
Income growth
1.
Income level
2.
Conservatism
VII.
Systematically Biased Beliefs About Other Subjects?
VIII.
The Enlightened
Preference Approach